Saturday, May 19, 2012

4:23 PM 5/19/2012 - Psychiatrist who championed 'gay cure' admits he was wrong - The Guardian

Google Reader - Mike Nova's starred items
4:23 PM 5/19/2012 - Mike Nova's starred items
 
 


New York Times

Psychiatry Giant Sorry for Backing Gay 'Cure'
New York Times
Dr. Robert L. Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, lay awake at 4 o'clock on a recent morning knowing he had to do the one thing that comes least naturally to him. He pushed himself up and staggered into the dark.
Psychiatrist who championed 'gay cure' admits he was wrongThe Guardian
Psychiatrist apologizes for gay 'cure' studyMinneapolis Star Tribune
Psychiatrist apologizes for study on gay 'cure'ork Times.)Albany Times Union
Fort Worth Star Telegram -Medical Daily
all 200 news articles »


Sarasota Herald-Tribune

Doctor disavows research on 'gay cure'
Sarasota Herald-Tribune
“People with a shared worldview basically came together and created their own set of experts to offer alternative policy views,” said Dr. Jack Drescher, a psychiatrist in New York and co-editor of “Ex-Gay Research: Analyzing the Spitzer Study and Its ...
Psychiatrist disavows 'gay cure' researchWND.com
It's Time to Ban Reparative TherapyHuffington Post
Researcher apologizes for study of gay therapynews9.com KWTV
Everyday Health
all 202 news articles »

via psychiatry - Google Blog Search by EMB on 5/18/12
Psychiatry seems endlessly political. Having read Ronald Bayer's excellent chronicle of the story of homosexuality being read out of psychiatry's Diagnostic and Statistical Manual I was puzzled when I read the New York ...


Sarasota Herald-Tribune

Noted psychiatrist apologizes for study on gay 'cure'
Waterloo Record
And then it was done: a short letter to be published this month, in the same journal where the original study appeared. “I believe,” it concludes, “I owe the gay community an apology.” The idea to study reparative therapy at all was pure Spitzer, ...
Pioneer Pyschiatrist Robert Spitzer Apologizes For 2001 Ex-Gay Study. Should ...Queerty

all 13 news articles »


Noted psychiatrist apologizes for study on gay 'cure'
Waterloo Record
And he would learn later that a World Health Organization report, released Thursday, calls the therapy “a serious threat to the health and well-being — even the lives — of affected people.” Spitzer's fingers jerked over the keys, unreliably, ...

and more »


Sarasota Herald-Tribune

Doctor disavows research on 'gay cure'
Sarasota Herald-Tribune
Dr. Robert L. Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, turns 80 next week. Dr. Robert L. Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, who turns 80 next week, lay awake at 4 o'clock on a recent morning ...

and more »

via psychiatry research - Google Blog Search by -NO AUTHOR- on 5/18/12
(NEW YORK TIMES) — The simple fact was that he had done something wrong, and at the end of a long and revolutionary career it didn't matter how often he'd been right, how powerful he once was, or what it would mean for ...


Austin American-Statesman

Noted psychiatrist apologizes for study on 'gay cure'
Austin American-Statesman
As part of a technology change, commenting will not be available on some articles for a number of months. Read more about the change here. By Benedict Carey PRINCETON, NJ — The simple fact was that he had done something wrong, and at the end of a long ...
Researcher apologizes for study of gay therapyThe Seattle Times
Psychologist Recants Gay Cure StudyEveryday Health

all 175 news articles »

After more than 13000 international psychiatrists signed a petition objecting to the way the manual was being revised, the US psychiatrist heading the review committee, in an opinion piece in The New York Times this week, ...

Mike Nova's starred items


On Top Magazine

Doctor recants claim that reparative therapy can "cure" homosexuality
Denver Post
By Benedict Carey PRINCETON, nj —Dr. Robert Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, lay awake at 4 o'clock on a recent morning knowing he had to do the thing that comes least naturally to him.
Researcher recants study supporting gay 'cure'Sacramento Bee
Noted psychiatrist apologizes for study on gay 'cure'Waterloo Record

all 198 news articles »


The Guardian

Doctor recants claim that reparative therapy can "cure" homosexuality
Denver Post
By Benedict Carey PRINCETON, nj —Dr. Robert Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, lay awake at 4 o'clock on a recent morning knowing he had to do the thing that comes least naturally to him.
Researcher recants study supporting gay 'cure'Sacramento Bee
Doctor disavows research on 'gay cure'Sarasota Herald-Tribune

all 200 news articles »


Austin American-Statesman

Dr. Robert Spitzer recants study on 'curing' gays
San Francisco Chronicle
Dr. Robert Spitzer, 79, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, lay awake on a recent morning knowing he had to do the one thing that comes least naturally to him. Spitzer suffers from Parkinson's disease and has trouble walking, ...
Noted psychiatrist apologizes for study on 'gay cure'Austin American-Statesman
Researcher apologizes for study of gay therapyThe Seattle Times
Psychologist Recants Gay Cure StudyEveryday Health

all 200 news articles »

Clck Here to Read: Psychiatry Giant Sorry for Backing Gay 'Cure' by By Benedict Carey in The New York Times on May 18, 2012. Dr. Robert L. Spitzer is a major architect of the modern classification of mental disorders.

via psychiatry - Google Blog Search by news on 5/19/12
Psychiatry Giant Sorry for Backing Gay 'Cure' New York Times Dr. Robert L. Spitzer, considered by some to be the father of modern psychiatry, lay awake at 4 o'clock on a recent morning knowing he had to do the one thing that comes least ...


The Guardian

Noted psychiatrist Robert Spitzer apologizes for study on gay 'cure'
Tampabay.com
And he would learn later that a World Health Organization report, released Thursday, calls the therapy "a serious threat to the health and well-being — even the lives — of affected people." Spitzer's fingers jerked over the keys, unreliably, ...
Doctor recants claim that reparative therapy can "cure" homosexualityDenver Post
Researcher recants study supporting gay 'cure'Sacramento Bee

all 201 news articles »


A Noted Psychiatrist Said Gays Can Become Straight. Now He Says He's Wrong ...
Huffington Post
In 1999, Dr. Robert L. Spitzer, considered by some to be "the father of modern psychiatry," interviewed 200 men and women who had undergone "conversion" therapy. Now, 11 years later, he's recanted and apologized. His study was flawed, he says.

At the heart of the issue is the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM) – psychiatry's diagnostic “bible” (see main story). Allen Frances, who headed the last major rewrite of the manual – DSM-IV – fears ...

via psychiatric diagnosis - Google Blog Search by Tim Desmond, LMFT on 5/5/12
Is there Any Value In Psychiatric Diagnosis? The medical model of diagnosis has become a dominant idea in the field of mental health, but it hasn't always been this way. As a therapist, I will explore whether mental health ...

Thursday, May 17, 2012

FBI Behavioral Analysis Unit (BAU)

FBI Behavioral Analysis Unit (BAU)

FBI Behavioral Analysis Unit (BAU)

by Shelly on May 11, 2012
Share on Twitter
Submit to StumbleUpon
File:FBISeal.pngThe FBI’s Podcasts and Radio page offers a fascinating account of what it’s like to be a Behavioral Analyst. “Making sense of the incomprehensible. That’s the specialty of the eight agents of the FBI’s Behavioral Analysis Unit-2, or BAU-2”, shares FBI’s Mollie Halpern. “They get inside the twisted minds of serial murderers like Ted Bundy, Jeffrey Dahmer, and John Allen Muhammed”.
Contrary to fictional depictions, members of the BAU are not necessarily called out to crime scenes or in charge of an investigation; many times they act as consultants, sharing their expertise in order to contribute to cases being closed. FBI Behavioral Analysts are assigned to work for the National Center for the Analysis of Violent Crime (NCAVC) based in Quantico and each FBI field office is staffed with a NCAVC supervisory agent.
The NCVAC has four Behavioral Analysis Units: BAU-1 deals with counterterrorism/threat assessment, the BAU-2 deals with crimes where adults are the victims, BAU-3 deals with cases where children are the victims and the BAU-4 focuses on ViCAP. ViCAP stands for the Violent Criminal Apprehension Program which has the largest database of violent crimes, including murder, abductions, and sexual assaults, in the United States.
So while members of the BAU may not lead SWAT teams into a suspect’s home, physically chase after a fugitive or directly interrogate potential criminals, they do play vital and intriguing roles in assisting law enforcement agencies, such as developing the profile of an Unsub, providing key recommendations for how to interview a suspect, assessing threats, providing information to legal counsel and many more.
“The type of cases we get involved in … are the type of cases that the average individual struggles to understand themselves,” states the FBI’s BAU-2 Mark A. Hilts. “Why would somebody kill 10 different people over a year’s time period? What kind of person would chop somebody up or would carve something into a victim or would do some other bondage or other type of activity?”
If you’re interested in working for NCAVC as a Behavioral Analyst with the FBI, a degree in behavioral or forensic science, criminal justice or criminology would be extremely helpful. Those who wish to work for the NCVAC are eligible after they’ve served a minimum of three years as a special agent. However, many of these supervisory special agents have at least eight years experience with the FBI before being considered for a promotion to the NCVAC. Naturally, exemplary service as a special agent will increase your chances of being promoted to the BAU. “The most important qualifications include overall experience as an investigator specializing in violent crimes, particularly homicides, rapes, child abductions, and threats”, states the FBI Career Page.

Keys to References and Links

Keys to References and Links:


Hyperlinked: preferred citation

A: 1,2,3... - scientific journal articles

B: ... - books

N: ... - news items from general media

GS - Google Search

GSS - Google Scholar Search

GSN - Google News Search

GBS - Google Blogs Search

PM: 1, 2, 3... - Pubmed Search and citations

PM - rss - Pubmed Search RSS

W - Wikipedia Articles


_________________________________________________


Tuesday, May 15, 2012

Mental Illness (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Mental Illness (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

Mental Illness

First published Fri Nov 30, 2001; substantive revision Mon Feb 22, 2010
Psychiatry involves theories of the mind, theories of the causes of mental disorders, classification schemes for those disorders, research about the disorders, proven treatments and research into new treatments, and a number of professions whose job it is to work with or on behalf of people with mental disorders. The philosophical study of psychiatry discusses conceptual, ethical, metaphysical, social, and epistemological issues that arise in all these aspects of psychiatry. Central to this study is the nature of mental illness.
The central philosophical debate over mental illness is not about its existence, but rather over how to define it, and whether it can be given a scientific or objective definition, or whether normative and subjective elements are essential to our concept of mental illness. One desideratum for a successful definition of mental illness is that it will settle debates over particular purported mental illnesses.
The connection between philosophical issues in the study and treatment of mental illness and these other areas of philosophy is in many cases obvious, as in the question of when and how people with mental disorders are responsible for their actions is connected with the insanity defense in law, and the more general debate over the justification of punishment. The philosophical investigation of the nature of mental illness is therefore relevant to many other areas of philosophy. While there is no sharp divide between the philosophical discussion of the nature of mental illness and the wider philosophical discussion of psychiatry, we can focus on four major issues that have preoccupied the philosophical literature.

What can philosophy do for psychiatry?

What can philosophy do for psychiatry?

World Psychiatry. 2004 October; 3(3): 130–135.
PMCID: PMC1414692
What can philosophy do for psychiatry?
Kenneth WM Fulford,1,2,3 Giovanni Stanghellini,3,4 and Matthew Broome3,5
1Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick, Coventry, UK
2Department of Psychiatry, University of Oxford, UK
3WPA Section on Philosophy and Humanities in Psychiatry
4Department of Mental Health, University of Florence, Italy
5Institute of Psychiatry, University of London, UK
Abstract
This article illustrates the practical impact of recent developments in the philosophy of psychiatry in five key areas: patient-centred practice, new models of service delivery, neuroscience research, psychiatric education, and the organisation of psychiatry as an international science-led discipline focused on patient care. We conclude with a note on the role of philosophy in countering the stigmatisation of mental disorder.
Keywords: Concepts of disorder, classification, neuroimaging, early diagnosis, values-based practice, patient-centred practice
According to the great 20th century psychologist and philosopher William James, philosophy is "an unusually stubborn effort to think clearly" (1). The need for clear thinking in psychiatry arises from the fact that our subject raises problems of meaning alongside empirical difficulties in a particularly acute way. A recent Forum in World Psychiatry, dealing with "the challenge of psychiatric comorbidity" (2), makes the point. That Forum covered empirical issues such as the likely impact on psychiatric classifications of future advances in behavioural genetics (2, 3), but much of the debate was about conceptual difficulties; about the meanings, for example, of such key terms as "disease" and "disorder" (4), and "syndrome" (5); about the tension between "reliability" and various aspects of "validity" (6); and about the competing claims of categorical and dimensional classifications to reflect "the state of nature, not merely how clinicians think about the state of nature" (7).
As Allen Frances pointed out in his role as Chairperson of the DSM-IV Task Force (8), it is one thing to recognise the importance of conceptual difficulties in psychiatry, it is quite another to do something about them. In this article, therefore, we will be focusing not on problems but on solutions. The last few years have witnessed a remarkable explosion of cross-disciplinary work between philosophy and psychiatry (9). Rather than attempting a full review of the field, however, we will be illustrating what philosophy can do for psychiatry, with examples of what it is already doing in five key areas: a) patient-centred practice, b) models of service delivery, c) research, d) education and e) international organisations.
Philosophy, through a new model linking values with evidence, called values-based practice (VBP), gives us specific tools to help make science work for us in a more patient centred way (10). VBP is the theory and skills-base for effective healthcare decision-making where different (and hence potentially conflicting) values are involved. VBP, somewhat like a political democracy, starts from respect for different values and relies on good process for its practical effectiveness.
Good process in VBP, as shown in Table Table1, depends1, depends on 10 key "pointers". The starting point of good process in VBP is careful attention to individual patients' values (pointer 1). Where values conflict, however, VBP seeks to achieve a balanced approach to clinical decision-making by drawing on a range of different value perspectives, represented here by the multi-disciplinary team (pointer 2). Achieving a balance of value perspectives in turn depends on four key clinical skills: raising awareness, reasoning skills, knowledge and communication skills (pointers 3 to 6). Values-based and evidence-based approaches, as the next three pointers (pointers 7 to 9) indicate, are complementary. In particular, as David Sackett, one of the leaders of evidence-based practice, has emphasised, they are both essential to building genuine partnership between professionals, their patients and their patients' families (11). This aspect of good process in VBP is reflected in the partnership model of decision-making summarised in Table Table11 in pointer 10.
Table 1
Table 1
Ten pointers to good process in values-based practice
The philosophical sources of VBP include abstract formal disciplines such as linguistic analysis, phenomenology and hermeneutics (10). But its practical applications already include a number of both treatment (12) and policy and service development initiatives within the Modernisation Agency of the UK's National Health Service (www.connects.org.uk/conferences). Central to all these initiatives, is a training workbook covering the skills of VBP (13). This workbook, which is the result of a unique collaboration between a Philosophy Department (at Warwick University) and an in-service training provider (the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health), has been recently launched in London by the Minister of State responsible for mental health, Rosie Winterton, and will be the basis for training of front-line clinical staff from April of next year in each of the main national health service (NHS) regions of England and Wales.
Future developments in VBP will be supported by a lively international programme of ongoing research. A particular focus of this research is the role of values in classification and diagnosis. The American psychiatrist and co-editor (with Fulford) of the international journal Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, John Sadler, has been particularly active in this field (14, 15). A research methods meeting last year in London, funded by the UK government, brought together work on values in diagnosis from phenomenological (16, 17) and empirical (18) as well as philosophical sources. This work will contribute to the development of more inclusive models of psychiatric classification through the work of the WPA Sections on Philosophy and Humanities in Psychiatry and on Classification, Diagnostic Assessment and Nomenclature (19).
There is also ongoing educational research. Werdie van Staden, a psychiatrist and philosopher at Pretoria University, and founder, with Tuviah Zabow at Capetown University, of the Philosophy Special Interest Group in the South African Society of Psychiatrists, has established a joint educational research programme with Warwick University Medical School, dealing with the effectiveness of training in VBP for medical students.
Mental health services in many parts of the world are nowadays delivered by multi-disciplinary teams. This ensures that a variety of different skills– medical, psychological, social, etc. – are available to meet the needs of individual patients. However, team working is too often associated with conflicts and failures of communication, with the result that patients are at risk of "falling through the net" through lack of collaborative decision-making (20). In addition, there are some cultures with very different models of disorder altogether, for example where families and social networks are valued more highly than individual autonomy (21).
In a study combining philosophical work on concepts of disorder with empirical social science methods, Anthony Colombo and colleagues at Warwick University have shown that such difficulties in multi-disciplinary team working are often driven by unrecognised differences in models of disorder (22). Despite the contested status of the concept of mental disorder, most mental health professionals nowadays claim to work within a shared biopsychosocial model (23). But what Colombo et al's study showed is that in practice, and often without being aware of it, different professional disciplines actually work with very different implicit models Рhence the conflicts and difficulties in multi-disciplinary teamworking. Studies paralleling Colombo et al's project are currently underway at Link̦ping University in Sweden and at the Maudsley Hospital in London.
Colombo et al's study illustrates one of the general roles of philosophy in psychiatry. As the Oxford philosopher J. L. Austin put it, the characteristic output of philosophical "clear thinking" is to give us a more complete picture of the full meanings of the complex concepts by which we make sense of the world around us (24).
Phenomenology, and its close relatives existentialism and hermeneutics, are particularly helpful in giving us a "more complete" picture. Phenomenology, as Karl Jaspers (25, 26) recognised, provides a range of practical tools for working with personal meanings, alongside scientific findings, in psychopathology. This is important in research (see below). But phenomenology and related disciplines are already generating new models of service delivery more directly geared to individual and cultural meanings. Such models include the Irish psychiatrist and philosopher Patrick Bracken's use of Heideggerian phenomenology to support new approaches to the management of post-traumatic stress disorder in traditional societies (27), the American psychologist and philosopher Steven Sabat's use of discursive analysis to improve communication with Alzheimer's disease sufferers (28), and the Dutch philosopher Guy Widdershoven's work on collaborative decision-making, also in Alzheimer's disease, employing the "hermeneutic circle" (29).
It is no coincidence that the emergence of a new and vigorous philosophy of psychiatry in the closing years of the 20th century coincided with dramatic advances in the neurosciences (9). As no less a neuroscientist than Nancy Andreasen has pointed out, the neurosciences themselves are among the factors pushing traditional philosophical problems, such as the nature of personal identity and of our knowledge of "other minds", to the top of our agenda in psychiatry (30).
The new philosophy of psychiatry is certainly not shy of problems of this magnitude (31-33). The British psychiatrist Sean Spence's brain imaging studies of hysteria, for example, raise a number of the traditional problems of psychiatry in exactly the challenging way that Andreasen anticipated (34), and a joint research programme between Warwick and Oxford Universities and the Institute of Psychiatry in London, funded by the McDonnell-Pew Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience in Oxford, has brought together philosophers, neuroscientists and patients, in a collaborative study of schizophrenia published as a special double issue of Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, edited by the Warwick philosopher Christoph Hoerl (35).
It is however particularly through the phenomenological tradition, with its focus on subjective experience, that the new philosophy of psychiatry is connecting most directly with neuroscience research (36-39). Imaging studies, in particular, demand more sophisticated ways of characterising and defining the contents of experience and how these are linked to brain functioning (40, 41). The work of the Cologne group on early detection and prediction of psychotic illnesses, for example, draws directly on phenomenological methods (42). Research in this area is a two way process, however, in which phenomenology and philosophy of mind also draw on the rich varieties of psychopathology (43, 44).
Early in the field with the potential applications of phenomenology to psychopathology was of course Karl Jaspers (45), perhaps the first philosopher-psychiatrist. Building on a strong 20th century tradition of conceptually informed work on classification and diagnosis (46, 47), the new philosophy of psychiatry has picked up Jaspers' concern to link meanings with causes in psychopathology (48-51). But a strong tradition of phenomenological work was maintained through much of the 20th century in a number of European countries (notably France, Germany and Italy), in Japan and in South America (9).
It is impossible within the scope of this article even to list the many distinguished recent contributors to this tradition. The main areas of work include both specific symptoms (52-55) and wider issues of psychiatric nosology (56). Examples of work in this area, drawing on the phenomenologies of such seminal 20th century philosophers as Martin Heiddegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean Paul Sartre, are included in a number of recent collections (9, 57); new work is reviewed regularly in the History and Philosophy section of Current Opinion in Psychiatry (e.g., 58); and a more comprehensive treatment will be given in one of the volumes in the new book series from Oxford University Press on International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry (59).
Research in the philosophy of psychiatry requires the same high-level skills as in any other technical discipline. When it comes to education and training, however, philosophy has a wider contribution to make to psychiatry, through the development of the generic thinking skills, the "clear thinking" of William James' aphorism (above), that are essential in all areas of practice.
The training manual for VBP noted above is a well-developed example of the effectiveness of philosophy in this respect (13). The exercises used for the development of VBP-skills are based directly on ideas from philosophers such as J.L. Austin (24) and R.M. Hare (60), working in the most abstract areas of philosophical value theory. Yet, these training exercises have been particularly well received, in pilot studies, not by academic psychiatrists, but by patient advocates, mental health nurses, social workers and others, working in such challenging areas of front-line mental health practice as crisis intervention and assertive outreach (61).
A full curriculum for philosophy of psychiatry has been introduced in the latest revision of the Royal College of Psychiatrists' curriculum for higher psychiatric training, the "MRCPsych" (62). Besides other sources cited in this article, training in this area will build on rich resources from classical philosophy (63, 64) and history of ideas (65, 66).
Psychiatry is peculiar among medical disciplines in being particularly vulnerable to abusive uses for purposes of political or social control. The notorious "delusions of reformism", the basis on which political dissidents were diagnosed with "schizophrenia" in the former Soviet Union, is but one example of our vulnerability in this respect (67).
The prevention of such abuses involves a wide range of resources –political, scientific, legal and educational. Philosophy contributes generally in each of these areas, drawing on cross-cultural (68) and historical (69, 70) scholarship and political philosophy (71). Among other results, such work shows that the underlying vulnerability of psychiatry in this respect arises from a failure to maintain a balance of different perspectives. In the Soviet Union, it was the unbalanced dominance of the Soviet ethic that distorted diagnostic judgements (72). This led to a kind of conceptual blindness arising from what the 17th century political philosopher, and founder of British empiricism, John Locke, called "enthusiasms" (73). We have seen similar "enthusiasms" in psychiatry throughout the 20th century– for psychoanalysis at one stage in America, for example, and more recently, in some quarters, for a narrow model of "biological psychiatry" (74).
We can counter such "enthusiasms" only by maintaining what Jim Birley, a Past President of the Royal College of Psychiatrists, and founder chair of the reforming organisation Geneva Initiative for Psychiatry, has called an "open society" in international psychiatry (75). The new philosophy of psychiatry will contribute to maintaining such an open society, partly through the more complete picture of the conceptual structure of the subject which, as noted above, is its characteristic output, but also, and importantly, through its own organisation as an open and collegial discipline, inclusive of methodological pluralism, and embracing intellectual and cultural diversity (9).
Future international developments in the philosophy of psychiatry will be supported by an International Network for Philosophy and Psychiatry (INPP), launched from South Africa as part of the 2002 biennial meeting of the South African Society of Psychiatrists, hosted by Professors Tuviah Zabow and Werdie van Staden. The INPP has been set up to support local, national and subject based organisations. Collaborating closely with new Sections in both the WPA and the European Psychiatric Association, the INPP will aim to contribute to the development of international psychiatry as a strongly dynamic "open society" of the kind Jim Birley envisaged.
Perhaps the deepest difficulty with which psychiatry ended the 20th century was the continuing stigmatisation to which both patients and practitioners were subject. Despite developments in the neurosciences, psychiatry was still perceived by many as being somehow "unscientific" (76), and mental disorders continued to carry unwarranted negative associations such as violence and untreatability (12).
Philosophy, in giving us a more complete picture of the conceptual structure of psychiatry, shows that our subject, far from being scientifically deficient, is simply a good deal more difficult than other areas of healthcare. Philosophy is important in psychiatry for much the same reason that it is important in theoretical physics. Both disciplines demand clear thinking about concepts as well as sophisticated scientific instruments for gathering data.
As we enter the 21st century, however, other areas of medicine, besides psychiatry, will increasingly face conceptual difficulties driven by scientific advances (77). In engaging with philosophy, therefore, across the five key areas outlined in this article, psychiatry, far from running second to the rest of medicine as it did in the 20th century, is leading the way for 21st century medical science.
Acknowledgement
The Table is based on a figure published in Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Whose values? A workbook for values-based practice in mental health care. London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health (in press), and we are grateful to the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health in London for permission to reproduce it here.
1. James W. Essays, comments and reviews. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1987. Review of Grunzuge der Physiologischen Psychologie, by Wilhelm Wundt (1975) p. 296.
2. Pincus HA, Tew JD, First MB. Psychiatric comorbidity: is more less? World Psychiatry. 2004;3:18–23.
3. Regier DA. State-of-the-art psychiatric diagnosis. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:25–26.
4. Cooper J. Disorders are different from diseases. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:24.
5. Jablensky A. The syndrome – an antidote to spurious comorbidity? World Psychiatry. 2004;3:24–25.
6. Murthy RS. Psychiatric comorbidity presents special challenges in developing countries. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:28.
7. Lilienfeld SO, Waldman RD. Comorbidity and Chairman Mao. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:26–27.
8. Frances A. Preface. In: Sadler JZ, Wiggins OP, Schwartz MA, editors. Philosophical perspectives on psychiatric diagnostic classification. vii-ix. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 1994.
9. Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al. Past improbable, future possible: the renaissance in philosophy and psychiatry. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 1–41.
10. Fulford KWM. Ten principles of values-based medicine. In: Radden J, editor. The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. New York: Oxford University Press; 2004. pp. 205–234.
11. Sackett DL, Straus SE, Scott Richardson W, et al. Evidence-based medicine: how to practice and teach EBM. 2nd ed. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone; 2000.
12. Allott P, Loganathan L, Fulford KWM. Discovering hope for recovery. Can J Commun Ment Health. 2002;21:13–33.
13. Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Whose values? A workbook for values-based practice in mental health care. London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health; (in press)
14. Sadler JZ. Epistemic value commitments in the debate over categorical vs. dimensional personality diagnosis. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;3:203–222.
15. Sadler JZ, editor. Descriptions and prescriptions: values, mental disorders, and the DSMs. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2002.
16. Stanghellini G. Vulnerability to schizophrenia and lack of common sense. Schizophr Bull. 2000;26:775–787.[PubMed]
17. Stanghellini G. Deanimated bodies and disembodied spirits. Essays on the psychopathology of common sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2004.
18. Tan JOA, Hope T, Stewart A, et al. Competence to make treatment decisions in anorexia nervosa: thinking processes and values. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. (in press)
19. Mezzich JE. Comprehensive diagnosis: a conceptual basis for future diagnostic systems. Psychopathology. 2002;35:162–165.[PubMed]
20. Onyett S. Teamworking in mental health. Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan; 2003.
21. Okasha A. Ethics of psychiatric practice: consent, compulsion and confidentiality. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2000;13:693–698.
22. Colombo A, Bendelow G, Fulford KWM, et al. Evaluating the influence of implicit models of mental disorder on processes of shared decision making within community-based multi-disciplinary teams. Soc Sci Med. 2003;56:1557–1570.[PubMed]
23. Fulford KWM. Mental illness: definition, use and meaning. In: Post SG, editor. Encyclopedia of bioethics. 3rd ed. New York: Macmillan; 2003.
24. Austin JL. A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 1956-7;57:1-30. In: White AR, editor. The philosophy of action. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1968. pp. 19–42.
25. Jaspers K. (1913) Causal and meaningful connexions between life history and psychosis. In: Hirsch SR, Shepherd M, editors. Themes and variations in European psychiatry. Bristol: Wright; 1974. pp. 83–93.
26. Jaspers K. The phenomenological approach in psychopathology. Zeitschrift fur die Gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie. 1913;9:391–408. (Ger). (English translation: Br J Psychiatry 1968;114:1313-23)
27. Bracken P. Trauma: culture, meaning and philosophy. London: Whurr; 2002.
28. Sabat SR. The experience of Alzheimer's disease: life through a tangled veil. Oxford: Blackwell; 2001.
29. Widdershoven G, Widdershoven-Heerding I. Understanding dementia: a hermeneutic perspective. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 103–111.
30. Andreasen NC. Brave new brain: conquering mental illness in the era of the genome. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001.
31. Glover J. The philosophy and psychology of personal identity. London: Penguin; 1988.
32. Graham G, Lynn Stephens G. An introduction to philosophical psychopathology: its nature, scope, and emergence. In: Graham G, Lynn Stephens G, editors. Philosophical psychopathology. Cambridge: MIT Press; 1994. pp. 1–23.
33. Hobson P. The cradle of thought. London: MacMillan; 2002.
34. Spence SA. Free will in the light of neuropsychiatry. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;32:75–90.
35. Hoerl C. Introduction: understanding, explaining, and intersubjectivity in schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2001;8:83–88.
36. Sims A, Mundt C, Berner P, et al. Descriptive phenomenology. In: Gelder M, Lopez-Ibor JJ, Andreasen NC, editors. New Oxford textbook of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 55–70.
37. Parnas J, Zahavi D. The link: philosophy-psychopathology-phenomenology. In: Zahavi D, editor. Exploring the self. Amsterdam: Benjamins; 2000. pp. 1–16.
38. Pringuey D, Kohl FS, editors. Phenomenology of human identity and schizophrenia. Nice: Association Le Cercle Herméneutique, Société d'Anthropologie Phénologique et d'Herméneutique Générale;
39. Blankenburg W. Phänomenologie als Grundlagendisziplin der Psychiatrie. Fundamenta Psychiatrica. 1991;5:92–101.
40. Bolton D, Hill J. Mind, meaning and mental disorder: the nature of causal explanation in psychology and psychiatry. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2004.
41. Thornton T. Reasons and causes in philosophy and psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:307–318.
42. Klosterkotter J. Diagnosing schizophrenia in the initial prodromal phase. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2001;58:158–164.[PubMed]
43. Gipps R, Fulford KWM. Understanding the clinical concept of delusion: from an estranged to an engaged epistemology. Int Rev Psychiatry. (in press)
44. Wilkes KV. Real people: personal identity without thought experiments. Oxford: Clarendon; 1988.
45. Jaspers K. Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Berlin: Springer; 1913.
46. Wing JK, Cooper JE, Sartorius N. Measurement and classification of psychiatric symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1974.
47. Kendell RE. The role of diagnosis in psychiatry. Oxford: Blackwell; 1975.
48. Harré R. Pathological autobiographies. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:99–110.
49. Gillett G. The mind and its discontents. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1999.
50. Glas G. (2003) Anxiety - animal reactions and the embodiment of meaning. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 231–249.
51. Van Staden CW, Fulford KWM. Changes in semantic uses of first person pronouns as possible linguistic markers of recovery in psychotherapy. Aust N Zeal J Psychiatry. 2004;38:226–232.
52. Sass LA. The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Cornell: Cornell University Press; 1995.
53. Musalek M. Meanings and causes of delusions. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 155–169.
54. Morris KJ. The phenomenology of body dysmorphic disorder: a Sartrean analysis. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 270–274.
55. Heinimaa M. Incomprehensibility. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 217–230.
56. Kraus A. (2003) How can the phenomenological-anthropological approach contribute to diagnosis and classification in psychiatry? In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 199–216.
57. Radden J, editor. New York: Oxford University Press; The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. (in press)
58. Mishara AL, Parnas J, Naudin J. Forging the links between phenomenology, cognitive neuroscience, and psychopathology: the emergence of a new discipline. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 1998;11:567–573.
59. Parnas J, Sass L, Stanghellini G, et al. The vulnerable self: the clinical phenomenology of the schizophrenic and affective spectrum disorders. Oxford: Oxford University Press; (in press)
60. Hare RM. The language of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1952.
61. Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Good practice? Values-based practice in mental health. Mental Health Practice. 2003;7:30–34.
62. Royal College of Psychiatrists. Curriculum for basic specialist training and the MRCPsych examination. London: Royal College of Psychiatrists; 2001.
63. Nordenfelt L. The stoic conception of mental disorder: the case of Cicero. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:285–292.
64. Megone C. Aristotele's function argument and the concept of mental illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1998;5:187–202.
65. Arens K. Wilhelm Griesinger: psychiatry between philosophy and praxis. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;3:147–164.
66. Berrios GE. The history of mental symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1996.
67. Bloch S, Reddaway P. Russia's political hospitals: the abuse of psychiatry in the Soviet Union. London: Gollancz; 1997.
68. Hayashi M, Kitamura T. Euthanasia trials in Japan: implications for legal and medical practice. Int J Law Psychiatry. 2002;25:557–571.[PubMed]
69. Mundt CH. The history of psychiatry in Heidelberg. In: Spitzer M, Uehlein F, Schwartz MA, et al., editors. Phenomenology, language and schizophrenia. New York: Springer; 1992. pp. 16–31.
70. Robinson D. Wild beasts and idle humours. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1996.
71. Matthews E. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. Vol. 2. 1995. Moralist or therapist? Foucault and the critique of psychiatry; pp. 19–30.
72. Fulford KWM, Smirnoff AYU, Snow E. Concepts of disease and the abuse of psychiatry in the USSR. Br J Psychiatry. 1993;162:801–810.[PubMed]
73. Locke J. In: An essay concerning human understanding. Nidditch PH, editor. Oxford: Clarendon; 1979.
74. Kramer PD. Listening to Prozac. 2nd ed. Harmondsworth: Penguin; 1997.
75. Birley J. Psychiatric ethics: an international open society. In: Dickenson D, Fulford KWM, editors. Two minds: a casebook of psychiatric ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 327–335.
76. Phillips J. Conceptual models for psychiatry. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2000;13:683–688.
77. Fulford KWM. Teleology without tears: naturalism, neo-naturalism and evaluationism in the analysis of function statements in biology (and a bet on the twenty-first century) Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2000;7:77–94.