World Psychiatry. 2004 October; 3(3): 130–135. | PMCID: PMC1414692 |
Copyright World Psychiatric Association
What can philosophy do for psychiatry?
1Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick, Coventry, UK
2Department of Psychiatry, University of Oxford, UK
3WPA Section on Philosophy and Humanities in Psychiatry
4Department of Mental Health, University of Florence, Italy
5Institute of Psychiatry, University of London, UK
This article has been cited by other articles in PMC.
Abstract
This article illustrates the practical impact of recent developments in the philosophy of psychiatry in five key areas: patient-centred practice, new models of service delivery, neuroscience research, psychiatric education, and the organisation of psychiatry as an international science-led discipline focused on patient care. We conclude with a note on the role of philosophy in countering the stigmatisation of mental disorder.
Keywords: Concepts of disorder, classification, neuroimaging, early diagnosis, values-based practice, patient-centred practice
According to the great 20th century psychologist and philosopher William James, philosophy is "an unusually stubborn effort to think clearly" (1). The need for clear thinking in psychiatry arises from the fact that our subject raises problems of meaning alongside empirical difficulties in a particularly acute way. A recent Forum in World Psychiatry, dealing with "the challenge of psychiatric comorbidity" (2), makes the point. That Forum covered empirical issues such as the likely impact on psychiatric classifications of future advances in behavioural genetics (2, 3), but much of the debate was about conceptual difficulties; about the meanings, for example, of such key terms as "disease" and "disorder" (4), and "syndrome" (5); about the tension between "reliability" and various aspects of "validity" (6); and about the competing claims of categorical and dimensional classifications to reflect "the state of nature, not merely how clinicians think about the state of nature" (7).
As Allen Frances pointed out in his role as Chairperson of the DSM-IV Task Force (8), it is one thing to recognise the importance of conceptual difficulties in psychiatry, it is quite another to do something about them. In this article, therefore, we will be focusing not on problems but on solutions. The last few years have witnessed a remarkable explosion of cross-disciplinary work between philosophy and psychiatry (9). Rather than attempting a full review of the field, however, we will be illustrating what philosophy can do for psychiatry, with examples of what it is already doing in five key areas: a) patient-centred practice, b) models of service delivery, c) research, d) education and e) international organisations.
PATIENTS: PHILOSOPHY PUTS PATIENTS FIRST
Philosophy, through a new model linking values with evidence, called values-based practice (VBP), gives us specific tools to help make science work for us in a more patient centred way (10). VBP is the theory and skills-base for effective healthcare decision-making where different (and hence potentially conflicting) values are involved. VBP, somewhat like a political democracy, starts from respect for different values and relies on good process for its practical effectiveness.
Good process in VBP, as shown in Table Table1, depends1, depends on 10 key "pointers". The starting point of good process in VBP is careful attention to individual patients' values (pointer 1). Where values conflict, however, VBP seeks to achieve a balanced approach to clinical decision-making by drawing on a range of different value perspectives, represented here by the multi-disciplinary team (pointer 2). Achieving a balance of value perspectives in turn depends on four key clinical skills: raising awareness, reasoning skills, knowledge and communication skills (pointers 3 to 6). Values-based and evidence-based approaches, as the next three pointers (pointers 7 to 9) indicate, are complementary. In particular, as David Sackett, one of the leaders of evidence-based practice, has emphasised, they are both essential to building genuine partnership between professionals, their patients and their patients' families (11). This aspect of good process in VBP is reflected in the partnership model of decision-making summarised in Table Table11 in pointer 10.
The philosophical sources of VBP include abstract formal disciplines such as linguistic analysis, phenomenology and hermeneutics (10). But its practical applications already include a number of both treatment (12) and policy and service development initiatives within the Modernisation Agency of the UK's National Health Service (www.connects.org.uk/conferences). Central to all these initiatives, is a training workbook covering the skills of VBP (13). This workbook, which is the result of a unique collaboration between a Philosophy Department (at Warwick University) and an in-service training provider (the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health), has been recently launched in London by the Minister of State responsible for mental health, Rosie Winterton, and will be the basis for training of front-line clinical staff from April of next year in each of the main national health service (NHS) regions of England and Wales.
Future developments in VBP will be supported by a lively international programme of ongoing research. A particular focus of this research is the role of values in classification and diagnosis. The American psychiatrist and co-editor (with Fulford) of the international journal Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, John Sadler, has been particularly active in this field (14, 15). A research methods meeting last year in London, funded by the UK government, brought together work on values in diagnosis from phenomenological (16, 17) and empirical (18) as well as philosophical sources. This work will contribute to the development of more inclusive models of psychiatric classification through the work of the WPA Sections on Philosophy and Humanities in Psychiatry and on Classification, Diagnostic Assessment and Nomenclature (19).
There is also ongoing educational research. Werdie van Staden, a psychiatrist and philosopher at Pretoria University, and founder, with Tuviah Zabow at Capetown University, of the Philosophy Special Interest Group in the South African Society of Psychiatrists, has established a joint educational research programme with Warwick University Medical School, dealing with the effectiveness of training in VBP for medical students.
SERVICES: PHILOSOPHY SUPPORTS NEW MODELS OF SERVICE DELIVERY
Mental health services in many parts of the world are nowadays delivered by multi-disciplinary teams. This ensures that a variety of different skills– medical, psychological, social, etc. – are available to meet the needs of individual patients. However, team working is too often associated with conflicts and failures of communication, with the result that patients are at risk of "falling through the net" through lack of collaborative decision-making (20). In addition, there are some cultures with very different models of disorder altogether, for example where families and social networks are valued more highly than individual autonomy (21).
In a study combining philosophical work on concepts of disorder with empirical social science methods, Anthony Colombo and colleagues at Warwick University have shown that such difficulties in multi-disciplinary team working are often driven by unrecognised differences in models of disorder (22). Despite the contested status of the concept of mental disorder, most mental health professionals nowadays claim to work within a shared biopsychosocial model (23). But what Colombo et al's study showed is that in practice, and often without being aware of it, different professional disciplines actually work with very different implicit models – hence the conflicts and difficulties in multi-disciplinary teamworking. Studies paralleling Colombo et al's project are currently underway at Linköping University in Sweden and at the Maudsley Hospital in London.
Colombo et al's study illustrates one of the general roles of philosophy in psychiatry. As the Oxford philosopher J. L. Austin put it, the characteristic output of philosophical "clear thinking" is to give us a more complete picture of the full meanings of the complex concepts by which we make sense of the world around us (24).
Phenomenology, and its close relatives existentialism and hermeneutics, are particularly helpful in giving us a "more complete" picture. Phenomenology, as Karl Jaspers (25, 26) recognised, provides a range of practical tools for working with personal meanings, alongside scientific findings, in psychopathology. This is important in research (see below). But phenomenology and related disciplines are already generating new models of service delivery more directly geared to individual and cultural meanings. Such models include the Irish psychiatrist and philosopher Patrick Bracken's use of Heideggerian phenomenology to support new approaches to the management of post-traumatic stress disorder in traditional societies (27), the American psychologist and philosopher Steven Sabat's use of discursive analysis to improve communication with Alzheimer's disease sufferers (28), and the Dutch philosopher Guy Widdershoven's work on collaborative decision-making, also in Alzheimer's disease, employing the "hermeneutic circle" (29).
RESEARCH: PHILOSOPHY RE-CONNECTS MINDS WITH BRAINS IN RESEARCH
It is no coincidence that the emergence of a new and vigorous philosophy of psychiatry in the closing years of the 20th century coincided with dramatic advances in the neurosciences (9). As no less a neuroscientist than Nancy Andreasen has pointed out, the neurosciences themselves are among the factors pushing traditional philosophical problems, such as the nature of personal identity and of our knowledge of "other minds", to the top of our agenda in psychiatry (30).
The new philosophy of psychiatry is certainly not shy of problems of this magnitude (31-33). The British psychiatrist Sean Spence's brain imaging studies of hysteria, for example, raise a number of the traditional problems of psychiatry in exactly the challenging way that Andreasen anticipated (34), and a joint research programme between Warwick and Oxford Universities and the Institute of Psychiatry in London, funded by the McDonnell-Pew Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience in Oxford, has brought together philosophers, neuroscientists and patients, in a collaborative study of schizophrenia published as a special double issue of Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, edited by the Warwick philosopher Christoph Hoerl (35).
It is however particularly through the phenomenological tradition, with its focus on subjective experience, that the new philosophy of psychiatry is connecting most directly with neuroscience research (36-39). Imaging studies, in particular, demand more sophisticated ways of characterising and defining the contents of experience and how these are linked to brain functioning (40, 41). The work of the Cologne group on early detection and prediction of psychotic illnesses, for example, draws directly on phenomenological methods (42). Research in this area is a two way process, however, in which phenomenology and philosophy of mind also draw on the rich varieties of psychopathology (43, 44).
Early in the field with the potential applications of phenomenology to psychopathology was of course Karl Jaspers (45), perhaps the first philosopher-psychiatrist. Building on a strong 20th century tradition of conceptually informed work on classification and diagnosis (46, 47), the new philosophy of psychiatry has picked up Jaspers' concern to link meanings with causes in psychopathology (48-51). But a strong tradition of phenomenological work was maintained through much of the 20th century in a number of European countries (notably France, Germany and Italy), in Japan and in South America (9).
It is impossible within the scope of this article even to list the many distinguished recent contributors to this tradition. The main areas of work include both specific symptoms (52-55) and wider issues of psychiatric nosology (56). Examples of work in this area, drawing on the phenomenologies of such seminal 20th century philosophers as Martin Heiddegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean Paul Sartre, are included in a number of recent collections (9, 57); new work is reviewed regularly in the History and Philosophy section of Current Opinion in Psychiatry (e.g., 58); and a more comprehensive treatment will be given in one of the volumes in the new book series from Oxford University Press on International Perspectives in Philosophy and Psychiatry (59).
EDUCATION: PHILOSOPHY CONTRIBUTES TO GENERIC SKILLS TRAINING IN PSYCHIATRIC EDUCATION
Research in the philosophy of psychiatry requires the same high-level skills as in any other technical discipline. When it comes to education and training, however, philosophy has a wider contribution to make to psychiatry, through the development of the generic thinking skills, the "clear thinking" of William James' aphorism (above), that are essential in all areas of practice.
The training manual for VBP noted above is a well-developed example of the effectiveness of philosophy in this respect (13). The exercises used for the development of VBP-skills are based directly on ideas from philosophers such as J.L. Austin (24) and R.M. Hare (60), working in the most abstract areas of philosophical value theory. Yet, these training exercises have been particularly well received, in pilot studies, not by academic psychiatrists, but by patient advocates, mental health nurses, social workers and others, working in such challenging areas of front-line mental health practice as crisis intervention and assertive outreach (61).
A full curriculum for philosophy of psychiatry has been introduced in the latest revision of the Royal College of Psychiatrists' curriculum for higher psychiatric training, the "MRCPsych" (62). Besides other sources cited in this article, training in this area will build on rich resources from classical philosophy (63, 64) and history of ideas (65, 66).
ORGANISATIONS: PHILOSOPHY UNDERPINS AN 'INTERNATIONAL' OPEN SOCIETY IN MENTAL HEALTH
Psychiatry is peculiar among medical disciplines in being particularly vulnerable to abusive uses for purposes of political or social control. The notorious "delusions of reformism", the basis on which political dissidents were diagnosed with "schizophrenia" in the former Soviet Union, is but one example of our vulnerability in this respect (67).
The prevention of such abuses involves a wide range of resources –political, scientific, legal and educational. Philosophy contributes generally in each of these areas, drawing on cross-cultural (68) and historical (69, 70) scholarship and political philosophy (71). Among other results, such work shows that the underlying vulnerability of psychiatry in this respect arises from a failure to maintain a balance of different perspectives. In the Soviet Union, it was the unbalanced dominance of the Soviet ethic that distorted diagnostic judgements (72). This led to a kind of conceptual blindness arising from what the 17th century political philosopher, and founder of British empiricism, John Locke, called "enthusiasms" (73). We have seen similar "enthusiasms" in psychiatry throughout the 20th century– for psychoanalysis at one stage in America, for example, and more recently, in some quarters, for a narrow model of "biological psychiatry" (74).
We can counter such "enthusiasms" only by maintaining what Jim Birley, a Past President of the Royal College of Psychiatrists, and founder chair of the reforming organisation Geneva Initiative for Psychiatry, has called an "open society" in international psychiatry (75). The new philosophy of psychiatry will contribute to maintaining such an open society, partly through the more complete picture of the conceptual structure of the subject which, as noted above, is its characteristic output, but also, and importantly, through its own organisation as an open and collegial discipline, inclusive of methodological pluralism, and embracing intellectual and cultural diversity (9).
Future international developments in the philosophy of psychiatry will be supported by an International Network for Philosophy and Psychiatry (INPP), launched from South Africa as part of the 2002 biennial meeting of the South African Society of Psychiatrists, hosted by Professors Tuviah Zabow and Werdie van Staden. The INPP has been set up to support local, national and subject based organisations. Collaborating closely with new Sections in both the WPA and the European Psychiatric Association, the INPP will aim to contribute to the development of international psychiatry as a strongly dynamic "open society" of the kind Jim Birley envisaged.
CONCLUSIONS: PHILOSOPHY PUTS PSYCHIATRY FIRST
Perhaps the deepest difficulty with which psychiatry ended the 20th century was the continuing stigmatisation to which both patients and practitioners were subject. Despite developments in the neurosciences, psychiatry was still perceived by many as being somehow "unscientific" (76), and mental disorders continued to carry unwarranted negative associations such as violence and untreatability (12).
Philosophy, in giving us a more complete picture of the conceptual structure of psychiatry, shows that our subject, far from being scientifically deficient, is simply a good deal more difficult than other areas of healthcare. Philosophy is important in psychiatry for much the same reason that it is important in theoretical physics. Both disciplines demand clear thinking about concepts as well as sophisticated scientific instruments for gathering data.
As we enter the 21st century, however, other areas of medicine, besides psychiatry, will increasingly face conceptual difficulties driven by scientific advances (77). In engaging with philosophy, therefore, across the five key areas outlined in this article, psychiatry, far from running second to the rest of medicine as it did in the 20th century, is leading the way for 21st century medical science.
Acknowledgement
The Table is based on a figure published in Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Whose values? A workbook for values-based practice in mental health care. London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health (in press), and we are grateful to the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health in London for permission to reproduce it here.
References
1. James W. Essays, comments and reviews. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1987. Review of Grunzuge der Physiologischen Psychologie, by Wilhelm Wundt (1975) p. 296.
2. Pincus HA, Tew JD, First MB. Psychiatric comorbidity: is more less? World Psychiatry. 2004;3:18–23.
3. Regier DA. State-of-the-art psychiatric diagnosis. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:25–26.
4. Cooper J. Disorders are different from diseases. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:24.
5. Jablensky A. The syndrome – an antidote to spurious comorbidity? World Psychiatry. 2004;3:24–25.
6. Murthy RS. Psychiatric comorbidity presents special challenges in developing countries. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:28.
7. Lilienfeld SO, Waldman RD. Comorbidity and Chairman Mao. World Psychiatry. 2004;3:26–27.
8. Frances A. Preface. In: Sadler JZ, Wiggins OP, Schwartz MA, editors. Philosophical perspectives on psychiatric diagnostic classification. vii-ix. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 1994.
9. Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al. Past improbable, future possible: the renaissance in philosophy and psychiatry. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 1–41.
10. Fulford KWM. Ten principles of values-based medicine. In: Radden J, editor. The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. New York: Oxford University Press; 2004. pp. 205–234.
11. Sackett DL, Straus SE, Scott Richardson W, et al. Evidence-based medicine: how to practice and teach EBM. 2nd ed. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone; 2000.
12. Allott P, Loganathan L, Fulford KWM. Discovering hope for recovery. Can J Commun Ment Health. 2002;21:13–33.
13. Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Whose values? A workbook for values-based practice in mental health care. London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health; (in press)
14. Sadler JZ. Epistemic value commitments in the debate over categorical vs. dimensional personality diagnosis. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;3:203–222.
15. Sadler JZ, editor. Descriptions and prescriptions: values, mental disorders, and the DSMs. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2002.
16. Stanghellini G. Vulnerability to schizophrenia and lack of common sense. Schizophr Bull. 2000;26:775–787.[PubMed]
17. Stanghellini G. Deanimated bodies and disembodied spirits. Essays on the psychopathology of common sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2004.
18. Tan JOA, Hope T, Stewart A, et al. Competence to make treatment decisions in anorexia nervosa: thinking processes and values. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. (in press)
19. Mezzich JE. Comprehensive diagnosis: a conceptual basis for future diagnostic systems. Psychopathology. 2002;35:162–165.[PubMed]
20. Onyett S. Teamworking in mental health. Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan; 2003.
21. Okasha A. Ethics of psychiatric practice: consent, compulsion and confidentiality. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2000;13:693–698.
22. Colombo A, Bendelow G, Fulford KWM, et al. Evaluating the influence of implicit models of mental disorder on processes of shared decision making within community-based multi-disciplinary teams. Soc Sci Med. 2003;56:1557–1570.[PubMed]
23. Fulford KWM. Mental illness: definition, use and meaning. In: Post SG, editor. Encyclopedia of bioethics. 3rd ed. New York: Macmillan; 2003.
24. Austin JL. A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 1956-7;57:1-30. In: White AR, editor. The philosophy of action. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1968. pp. 19–42.
25. Jaspers K. (1913) Causal and meaningful connexions between life history and psychosis. In: Hirsch SR, Shepherd M, editors. Themes and variations in European psychiatry. Bristol: Wright; 1974. pp. 83–93.
26. Jaspers K. The phenomenological approach in psychopathology. Zeitschrift fur die Gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie. 1913;9:391–408. (Ger). (English translation: Br J Psychiatry 1968;114:1313-23)
27. Bracken P. Trauma: culture, meaning and philosophy. London: Whurr; 2002.
28. Sabat SR. The experience of Alzheimer's disease: life through a tangled veil. Oxford: Blackwell; 2001.
29. Widdershoven G, Widdershoven-Heerding I. Understanding dementia: a hermeneutic perspective. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 103–111.
30. Andreasen NC. Brave new brain: conquering mental illness in the era of the genome. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001.
31. Glover J. The philosophy and psychology of personal identity. London: Penguin; 1988.
32. Graham G, Lynn Stephens G. An introduction to philosophical psychopathology: its nature, scope, and emergence. In: Graham G, Lynn Stephens G, editors. Philosophical psychopathology. Cambridge: MIT Press; 1994. pp. 1–23.
33. Hobson P. The cradle of thought. London: MacMillan; 2002.
34. Spence SA. Free will in the light of neuropsychiatry. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;32:75–90.
35. Hoerl C. Introduction: understanding, explaining, and intersubjectivity in schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2001;8:83–88.
36. Sims A, Mundt C, Berner P, et al. Descriptive phenomenology. In: Gelder M, Lopez-Ibor JJ, Andreasen NC, editors. New Oxford textbook of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 55–70.
37. Parnas J, Zahavi D. The link: philosophy-psychopathology-phenomenology. In: Zahavi D, editor. Exploring the self. Amsterdam: Benjamins; 2000. pp. 1–16.
38. Pringuey D, Kohl FS, editors. Phenomenology of human identity and schizophrenia. Nice: Association Le Cercle Herméneutique, Société d'Anthropologie Phénologique et d'Herméneutique Générale;
39. Blankenburg W. Phänomenologie als Grundlagendisziplin der Psychiatrie. Fundamenta Psychiatrica. 1991;5:92–101.
40. Bolton D, Hill J. Mind, meaning and mental disorder: the nature of causal explanation in psychology and psychiatry. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2004.
41. Thornton T. Reasons and causes in philosophy and psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:307–318.
42. Klosterkotter J. Diagnosing schizophrenia in the initial prodromal phase. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2001;58:158–164.[PubMed]
43. Gipps R, Fulford KWM. Understanding the clinical concept of delusion: from an estranged to an engaged epistemology. Int Rev Psychiatry. (in press)
44. Wilkes KV. Real people: personal identity without thought experiments. Oxford: Clarendon; 1988.
45. Jaspers K. Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Berlin: Springer; 1913.
46. Wing JK, Cooper JE, Sartorius N. Measurement and classification of psychiatric symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1974.
47. Kendell RE. The role of diagnosis in psychiatry. Oxford: Blackwell; 1975.
48. Harré R. Pathological autobiographies. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:99–110.
49. Gillett G. The mind and its discontents. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1999.
50. Glas G. (2003) Anxiety - animal reactions and the embodiment of meaning. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 231–249.
51. Van Staden CW, Fulford KWM. Changes in semantic uses of first person pronouns as possible linguistic markers of recovery in psychotherapy. Aust N Zeal J Psychiatry. 2004;38:226–232.
52. Sass LA. The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Cornell: Cornell University Press; 1995.
53. Musalek M. Meanings and causes of delusions. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 155–169.
54. Morris KJ. The phenomenology of body dysmorphic disorder: a Sartrean analysis. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 270–274.
55. Heinimaa M. Incomprehensibility. In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 217–230.
56. Kraus A. (2003) How can the phenomenological-anthropological approach contribute to diagnosis and classification in psychiatry? In: Fulford KWM, Morris KJ, Sadler JZ, et al., editors. Nature and narrative: an introduction to the new philosophy of psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2003. pp. 199–216.
57. Radden J, editor. New York: Oxford University Press; The philosophy of psychiatry: a companion. (in press)
58. Mishara AL, Parnas J, Naudin J. Forging the links between phenomenology, cognitive neuroscience, and psychopathology: the emergence of a new discipline. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 1998;11:567–573.
59. Parnas J, Sass L, Stanghellini G, et al. The vulnerable self: the clinical phenomenology of the schizophrenic and affective spectrum disorders. Oxford: Oxford University Press; (in press)
60. Hare RM. The language of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1952.
61. Woodbridge K, Fulford KWM. Good practice? Values-based practice in mental health. Mental Health Practice. 2003;7:30–34.
62. Royal College of Psychiatrists. Curriculum for basic specialist training and the MRCPsych examination. London: Royal College of Psychiatrists; 2001.
63. Nordenfelt L. The stoic conception of mental disorder: the case of Cicero. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1997;4:285–292.
64. Megone C. Aristotele's function argument and the concept of mental illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1998;5:187–202.
65. Arens K. Wilhelm Griesinger: psychiatry between philosophy and praxis. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 1996;3:147–164.
66. Berrios GE. The history of mental symptoms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1996.
67. Bloch S, Reddaway P. Russia's political hospitals: the abuse of psychiatry in the Soviet Union. London: Gollancz; 1997.
68. Hayashi M, Kitamura T. Euthanasia trials in Japan: implications for legal and medical practice. Int J Law Psychiatry. 2002;25:557–571.[PubMed]
69. Mundt CH. The history of psychiatry in Heidelberg. In: Spitzer M, Uehlein F, Schwartz MA, et al., editors. Phenomenology, language and schizophrenia. New York: Springer; 1992. pp. 16–31.
70. Robinson D. Wild beasts and idle humours. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1996.
71. Matthews E. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. Vol. 2. 1995. Moralist or therapist? Foucault and the critique of psychiatry; pp. 19–30.
72. Fulford KWM, Smirnoff AYU, Snow E. Concepts of disease and the abuse of psychiatry in the USSR. Br J Psychiatry. 1993;162:801–810.[PubMed]
73. Locke J. In: An essay concerning human understanding. Nidditch PH, editor. Oxford: Clarendon; 1979.
74. Kramer PD. Listening to Prozac. 2nd ed. Harmondsworth: Penguin; 1997.
75. Birley J. Psychiatric ethics: an international open society. In: Dickenson D, Fulford KWM, editors. Two minds: a casebook of psychiatric ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000. pp. 327–335.
76. Phillips J. Conceptual models for psychiatry. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2000;13:683–688.
77. Fulford KWM. Teleology without tears: naturalism, neo-naturalism and evaluationism in the analysis of function statements in biology (and a bet on the twenty-first century) Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2000;7:77–94.
No comments:
Post a Comment